Well, what I had in mind was that the is-ought problem isn't a special insight into morality. We face the same issue in every area where humans divide the analog world into digital categories, and we don't let it stop us. How can we get from facts about how many legs something has and how tall it is and what color it is and so forth to a logical conclusion about whether it's a horse? It's not as though children are ever taught formal criteria for horseness and then run down a checklist and consequently conclude an animal with three legs can't be a horse because "quadruped" was in the definition. As children we just saw some horses and heard people call them "horses" and got the general idea. And now when we see a new animal we judge it a horse when the neural networks for horses that grew in our brains fire up. The foundation of thought isn't logic or science; it's pattern matching. And pattern matching is an eminently sensible way to draw conclusions. It's error-prone, true; but it's not as though we have a better alternative. Heck, the only justification we have for logic and science themselves is pattern matching. How do you know (NOT NOT A implies A), other than that it fits a pattern you've seen a thousand times that's never led you wrong?
So if I can't deductively prove you ought not torture people for fun without introducing some premise with "ought" in it that's more dubious than the desired conclusion, so what? I can't deductively prove Wizard was a horse either, without introducing some premise with "horse" in it that's more dubious than the desired conclusion. But that's not sufficient reason to conclude that I don't know whether he was a horse. I met Wizard a dozen times. He ate hay out of my hand. The same pattern recurs in every field of human inquiry. But it's only in morality where for some reason this routine puzzle of human psychology is commonly blown up into an argument for radical antirealism.
Hume made pretty much the same argument about two other philosophical conundrums: inductive reasoning (How do you get from a "was" to a "will") and causality (How do you get from a "happened after" to a "was caused by"). Some philosophers have certainly been known to take those objections seriously, but Hume's skepticism about induction and cause-and-effect never made its way into the public consciousness the way his moral skepticism did. Why is that? Does the you-can't-prove-it's-a-horse argument qualify as a better argument when you make it about morality than when you make it about other areas?
Anyway, that's why I think it's overrated. I hope it helps.
I won’t quibble, because I think I mostly (a) agree that the is-ought problem may be over-rated in the way you describe and (b) agree with what you say about the way we think, and thank you for the interesting insights and parallels.
Right. But I think the way people normally come up with moral theories is completely wrong-headed. They try to invent some principle from which all moral questions can be answered; then they infer that our moral intuitions are invalid unless the principle agrees with them. It's sort of like if Kepler had dealt with his dissatisfaction with the prevailing Ptolemaic model of the solar system by setting out to invent an explanation accounting for every phenomenon in the universe. If he'd tried that the result wouldn't have been a grand unified theory of quantum gravity; he'd have invented some gobbledygook about nature maximizing the glory of God or something. That's not the way to make progress -- reaching out too far into the unknown is recipe for "If the observations disagree with the theory they must be discarded." We'd do better to have a little modesty about our abilities, and work toward our general moral theory incrementally, finding limited explanations that handle small pieces of the overall problem, testing those explanations at every step of the way, checking if what they say still makes sense in some changed situation.
Ok, so, to me, this resort to human intuitions is what I think is a good feature (in the non-moral sense) about what I am going to call angra’s moral theory.
And while I agree with you that coming up with moral principles that conflict with typical human intuitions is a bit suspect, I'm as suspicious of claims that there are underlying moral truths (for example, entirely on the basis of human intuitions). I'm not a big fan of either, possibly for different reasons.
And I'm particularly wary of expressing certainty in such matters. I personally have not seen an unproblematic moral theory. I read of many, and some seem better than others, that's all. An ex-member of this forum used to say,
'the study of the human mind has not had its Isaac Newton yet' and I often think about that.
Well, that gets us into definitions of objective and relativist. Some people equate "objective" with "universal", or "certain", or "without exceptions", or "human-independent"; but personally, I'd define "objective morality" as meaning at least one moral claim is truth-apt and its truth doesn't depend on any observer's subjective opinion. As for "relativist", relative to what? To my mind the phrase refers to moral claims' truth depending on an observer's subjective opinion or preference. But there are other things truth could be relative to. "You shouldn't kill him." might well be true or false depending on whether the guy wants to be killed; but it seems to me that would not be a case of what is normally meant by "moral relativism". YMMV; in any event it's merely a semantic point. We don't need to agree on what's the best terminology as long as we're able to explain what we mean and translate our arguments into the various alternative moral languages.
To me defining "objective morality" as merely meaning
“at least one moral claim is truth-apt and its truth doesn't depend on any observer's subjective opinion” is what I might call a low bar.
For example, and only referring to the 'at least one' component, if a relativist can claim, to a similar extent, that at least one moral claim is relative, where does that leave the argument over whether morality is objective or relative? On a bell curve of some sort? Personally, I suspect that's the sort of thing we're talking about here. Something like a bell curve (with the vertical axis being ascending disagreement and the horizontal axis being different types of moral claim) And even at the extremes representing 'objectivity' I think it's a watered-down (perhaps better to say weak) definition of objectivity that's being used.
I don't see why anything would need to be independent of our species in order to be objective; after all, it's an objective fact what species we are. It's wrong for a man to kill his meat slowly in order to have more fun in the process; it isn't wrong for a cat to do it. Cats and humans are different kinds of animals; our brains are wired differently; a human who thinks like a cat is broken while a cat who thinks like a cat isn't broken.
Literally the first dictionary definition google threw up for me for ‘objective’ was
“not dependent on the mind for existence; actual". This is what I generally mean by ‘objective’ (and also ‘independent’). YMMV.
Situationally boggy doesn't bother me. To suppose situational bogginess conflicts with objectivity gets things precisely backwards. Situational morality is objective morality: objectivity is the whole reason it's possible in the first place to discredit a proposed moral rule by identifying a situation where it gives a nutty answer. "Self defense" is only able to situationally refute "Thou shalt not kill" because there's a right answer to whether it was morally permissible for Bruce Willis to use lethal force to stop Alan Rickman from shooting him. Without a right answer independent of opinion, a situation isn't what it takes to make an exception to a rule. All it takes is "Nuh-uh!".
(Of course, in a complicated world full of non-clear-cut situations, one might well worry that there's no end to exceptions, and you can never get a definitive answer to anything because for any possible moral judgment there always might be a situation you haven't thought of where it's wrong. The thing to keep in mind, though, is that this is only a problem for moral theories, not a problem for moral facts. You can always avoid the possibility of exceptions by specifying the situation completely: i.e., by considering a specific case instead of a generalization. "It's wrong to murder the President" might well be too situationally boggy to qualify as a moral fact, true; but "Booth ought not to have murdered Lincoln" can't be, because it isn't situationally boggy at all.)
I think somewhere in the middle of that (the bolded part) you seemed to assume that situational morality is objective morality?
I agree that situational variety does not necessary mean the absence of objectivity. However, what I would say is that I strongly doubt that the situational variegation we see in the real world is underlain with objective (even in the sense you mentioned above) moral facts, to the point that there would be recourse to these
‘if only the situation was specified completely’. Consider me very sceptical about that.
There may be at least one 'objective moral fact' (using what I am calling a weak definition of 'objective', and possibly 'fact' too) but if such a fact is not invoked by or involved in a particular situation (eg something not involving killing, let alone killing for fun) then why would I assume that a completely specified situation not involving such a fact is going to lead me back to an objective moral fact about that situation (or indeed about the response to it, such as the deserts, something we have been setting aside for a while now)?
Here's an afterthought. It seems to be the case that one very common type of situational difference is 'ingroup or outgroup' (friend or foe, like me or not like me) and that our intuitive sense of right and wrong varies accordingly. So, even if there were, by some definitions, an 'objective moral fact' about doing X to someone, it would often need to be amended, in many cases, to cater for that sort of situational difference. At the very least, I do not think this adds any weight to claims for objective moral facts, and I would say it weakens them. As, by the way, for me, does the specification about supposed
'normal, proper-functioning, rational' humans, which, apart from not even being species-wide, in some ways sounds a bit like
'as all right-thinking people would surely agree....". As does what I think is using a weak definition of objectivity. As does defining 'fact' as 'what is very widely agreed'. As does the bar being as low as 'at least one'. I suspect the chairs are merely, to some extent, being arranged on the deck of the ship by semantically-inclined passengers who really really want to know the ship's True
TM course, and think rearranging the deck chairs is going to help with finding that out. To clarify what i mean there, I think there is a tendency to define things into existence.
As such, I think my bottom line opinion is that there are, in the end, no objective moral facts (I don't mean 'facts about morality'; that humans have moral intuitions is, of course, a fact. I mean that something is actually either morally right or wrong). It's just that we have evolved to think and feel that there are. I know that's quite a strong claim, but if I had to put my neck on the chopping block while being open to having my head chopped off if I'm wrong, that's what I'd say. Imo, the guiding principles are probably the same amoral ones that rule every living thing in the universe. We're not that special. See the cartoon posted by me previously.
Now, even if that's true, we can still (and always have) come up with moral standards, obviously, albeit ones that have shifted around at least somewhat throughout history. And taking human intuitions into account is probably a good idea, up to a point. But as someone might once have said,
'I like pigs, I'm just not sure I could eat a whole hog'.
In other words I wouldn't buy the 'moral facts from intuitions' claim wholesale.
And then there's the naturalistic fallacy to watch out for too, or the is-ought issue, or whatever. Even if it is somewhat over-rated.
It is sometimes said of moral relativism that it leads to absurd conclusions, such as that there are no morals or ways to make moral judgements, but I don't see that as absurd. Actually, it's not even the case, there are of course ways to make moral judgements, it's just that under relativism they're not made on the basis of actual moral facts, that's all.
I think I'm a moral relativist much more than I am a moral realist or objectivist. If this leaves me uncertain, I think that's currently the best, most warranted place to be, all things considered.