PyramidHead
Contributor
Here I want to make a distinction between the common-sense way that people may be said to be optimistic or pessimistic, either looking forward to or dreading their future prospects, and the metaphysical/philosophical sense of those terms. It is sometimes said that this matter is totally subjective, and so no resolution about the value or disvalue of life can ever be brokered between the views. I think that's a dodge, a cop-out, akin to the slippery equivalence some would claim between religion and science. What tips the scales toward pessimism (again, not toward having a depressive attitude or hating everybody, but toward a negative evaluation of life as a whole) is recognizing the important difference between value IN life, which we are obliged to create and pursue, as opposed to the value OF life. I am setting out to dispel the myth that the latter is just a tally of the former, that life-in-itself is a forbidden or unintelligible concept that amounts to nothing other than a weighted sum of the good and bad things one experiences during one's life. We do not insist upon this dogmatic stance when evaluating other things: it is perfectly reasonable to talk about what makes a good or bad zombie movie in one discussion, and talk about whether zombie movies as a whole are good or bad in another; we can make rules and establish accords that govern the right way for nations to conduct warfare in one discussion, and talk about whether warfare should be conducted at all in another; we can compare the efficacy of anti-cholesterol drugs in one discussion, and talk about whether those drugs should be recommended at all in another; and so on. In each case, there is an "intra-" sphere of considerations that apply when evaluating elements within the thing, and a wider perspective that evaluates the thing as a thing.
Optimism and pessimism are on equal footing in the intra-world of experiences. Good experiences may outweigh the bad for some, and the reverse may be true for others. It all depends on circumstances. It's common to go from being rich to being poor and then back to being rich again. A rough year can be followed by a peaceful one. Sometimes it rains, sometimes it shines. I'm not disputing any of that, and the position I'm defending doesn't either. It's the wider perspective that I wish to explore here, and I'll start by pointing out something immediately apparent: on this level, something about the balance of good and bad is different. We are totally accustomed to hearing about the see-saw of experiences IN life, such that today I feel sick but tomorrow I'll feel better, today I got all my work done but tomorrow I'll be distracted, etc. Yet, it is inconceivable to hear: today I am old but tomorrow I'll be younger, today I'm far from the onset of senility but tomorrow I'll be even further, today I'm moving into a risk population for heart disease due to my age and tomorrow I'm moving out of that risk population. The direction is one-way. Julio Cabrera calls this a "structural asymmetry." While the goods and bads within a given life may roughly balance out, the direction of life itself when viewed from a detached point is relentlessly negative. He describes it in this way:
So, it's not that pessimism requires that all of the joys of life be ignored, or that we must look forward to our deaths; quite the opposite. It is the very fact that the joys of life are so beautiful that constitutes life's badness, for above and beyond the coming and going of experience is an inexorable depletion of those joys until they are gone. The very fact that we must cling desperately to life is evidence that we are placed in a terminal situation that does not respect our wishes. I would like to further emphasize this point, because if it is misunderstood then there can be no communication: optimism and pessimism of the common-sense variety (a happy or sad stance toward what goes on in life) are both attitudes that occur against the same backdrop, which can be described in fairly objective terms regardless of attitude: we are all situated in a state of constant decay, wearing down, languishing, attrition, slippage toward the universal indignity of old age, or interrupted by catastrophe before then. These facts cannot be disputed rationally, nor can it be claimed that they are not distasteful to beings like humans, who desire the opposite in all pursuits: flourishing, improvement, security, comfort, vitality, and success. That life can be enjoyed "in spite of" the backdrop of structural negativity means life would otherwise be suffered by virtue of it.
As Cabrera says, both the love of life and the fear of death are perfectly compatible with philosophical pessimism, and indeed are predicted by it. In order to prevent ourselves from disappearing, which we fear and despise, we are obliged to live vividly and passionately, to establish and hunker down in strongholds of relative permanence amid the prevailing atmosphere of loss. These are all intra-worldly creations and can be fantastically pleasurable, and to the extent that they soften or otherwise ameliorate the harshness of life they may grant someone happiness in their time on earth. Pessimism doesn't say any different. All that is being acknowledged is that we cannot mistake these reactionary measures for inherent positives of life. We should see them for what they are, and life for what it is, without losing sight of the difference between the positive values we are forced to invent inside of life, and the deeply negative value of life per se that requires us to do it.
I have not elaborated thus far on the full extent of the structural asymmetry of life, but it is not hard to imagine what it entails, and can be elucidated without sliding into the subjectivity of individual preference. One is "born terminal", already from the very start in a process of deterioration that must be regularly stemmed by interventions from others (at first) and oneself (later). The second law of thermodynamics guarantees this for us. Throughout life, we are visited by a gradual decline of all of the facilities that help us navigate the world, from disease, injury, and age. The possibility of happiness is only realized at some cost, but suffering can be gratuitous beyond all utility. Among all other animals, we possess the awareness of these factors, which gives us an advantage in making them easier to bear while simultaneously instilling a host of psychological disorders unique to our species. It is in this context, not on a neutral plane of perfect balance, that we conduct the business of developing projects to improve our situation. That many of these projects are relatively successful does not mitigate the need for them in the first place! The existence of the need, in the fiber of life as an inescapable magnetism, is what shows life's disvalue, and this is NOT refuted by the intra-worldly constructions we erect in defiance of it.
I define philosophical pessimism as the recognition of the negative value of life relative to the preferences of human beings. I am not defining it as a prediction about what may or may not happen within a certain life, nor a sour disposition toward the things in the world that are genuinely beautiful; what separates the pessimist from the optimist is the cringe that accompanies the appreciation of beauty by the pessimist, for he knows that all the machinations of the universe are conspiring to dismantle everything beautiful eventually, whether by destroying it in a single violent act or by removing from the equation anyone who would appreciate it. Pessimism can therefore inspire a deep compassion, borne out of the knowledge that nobody has any more value than anybody else (because everybody has none!). But even if pessimism of this kind did not have such an effect on the conscience, it would still be difficult, if not impossible, to defeat on rational grounds.
Optimism and pessimism are on equal footing in the intra-world of experiences. Good experiences may outweigh the bad for some, and the reverse may be true for others. It all depends on circumstances. It's common to go from being rich to being poor and then back to being rich again. A rough year can be followed by a peaceful one. Sometimes it rains, sometimes it shines. I'm not disputing any of that, and the position I'm defending doesn't either. It's the wider perspective that I wish to explore here, and I'll start by pointing out something immediately apparent: on this level, something about the balance of good and bad is different. We are totally accustomed to hearing about the see-saw of experiences IN life, such that today I feel sick but tomorrow I'll feel better, today I got all my work done but tomorrow I'll be distracted, etc. Yet, it is inconceivable to hear: today I am old but tomorrow I'll be younger, today I'm far from the onset of senility but tomorrow I'll be even further, today I'm moving into a risk population for heart disease due to my age and tomorrow I'm moving out of that risk population. The direction is one-way. Julio Cabrera calls this a "structural asymmetry." While the goods and bads within a given life may roughly balance out, the direction of life itself when viewed from a detached point is relentlessly negative. He describes it in this way:
This is the fundamental asymmetry: while the facts in life allow alternation, the facts of life (of the vital birth-dying process) do not allow it. This, of course, is not bad in an absolute sense, but bad in relation to a being like the human being [...] it means that beings like humans, with their nervous system, their brain, their sexuality, their mechanism of desire, etc., can not see their own decay as being something good; they live it as a gradual and irreversible loss of the good (and even very good) that they can do and be; all positive values are generated within life, and are generated as a systematic opposition against the irreversible and “one-way” fall of the mortal structure of being.
So, it's not that pessimism requires that all of the joys of life be ignored, or that we must look forward to our deaths; quite the opposite. It is the very fact that the joys of life are so beautiful that constitutes life's badness, for above and beyond the coming and going of experience is an inexorable depletion of those joys until they are gone. The very fact that we must cling desperately to life is evidence that we are placed in a terminal situation that does not respect our wishes. I would like to further emphasize this point, because if it is misunderstood then there can be no communication: optimism and pessimism of the common-sense variety (a happy or sad stance toward what goes on in life) are both attitudes that occur against the same backdrop, which can be described in fairly objective terms regardless of attitude: we are all situated in a state of constant decay, wearing down, languishing, attrition, slippage toward the universal indignity of old age, or interrupted by catastrophe before then. These facts cannot be disputed rationally, nor can it be claimed that they are not distasteful to beings like humans, who desire the opposite in all pursuits: flourishing, improvement, security, comfort, vitality, and success. That life can be enjoyed "in spite of" the backdrop of structural negativity means life would otherwise be suffered by virtue of it.
As Cabrera says, both the love of life and the fear of death are perfectly compatible with philosophical pessimism, and indeed are predicted by it. In order to prevent ourselves from disappearing, which we fear and despise, we are obliged to live vividly and passionately, to establish and hunker down in strongholds of relative permanence amid the prevailing atmosphere of loss. These are all intra-worldly creations and can be fantastically pleasurable, and to the extent that they soften or otherwise ameliorate the harshness of life they may grant someone happiness in their time on earth. Pessimism doesn't say any different. All that is being acknowledged is that we cannot mistake these reactionary measures for inherent positives of life. We should see them for what they are, and life for what it is, without losing sight of the difference between the positive values we are forced to invent inside of life, and the deeply negative value of life per se that requires us to do it.
I have not elaborated thus far on the full extent of the structural asymmetry of life, but it is not hard to imagine what it entails, and can be elucidated without sliding into the subjectivity of individual preference. One is "born terminal", already from the very start in a process of deterioration that must be regularly stemmed by interventions from others (at first) and oneself (later). The second law of thermodynamics guarantees this for us. Throughout life, we are visited by a gradual decline of all of the facilities that help us navigate the world, from disease, injury, and age. The possibility of happiness is only realized at some cost, but suffering can be gratuitous beyond all utility. Among all other animals, we possess the awareness of these factors, which gives us an advantage in making them easier to bear while simultaneously instilling a host of psychological disorders unique to our species. It is in this context, not on a neutral plane of perfect balance, that we conduct the business of developing projects to improve our situation. That many of these projects are relatively successful does not mitigate the need for them in the first place! The existence of the need, in the fiber of life as an inescapable magnetism, is what shows life's disvalue, and this is NOT refuted by the intra-worldly constructions we erect in defiance of it.
I define philosophical pessimism as the recognition of the negative value of life relative to the preferences of human beings. I am not defining it as a prediction about what may or may not happen within a certain life, nor a sour disposition toward the things in the world that are genuinely beautiful; what separates the pessimist from the optimist is the cringe that accompanies the appreciation of beauty by the pessimist, for he knows that all the machinations of the universe are conspiring to dismantle everything beautiful eventually, whether by destroying it in a single violent act or by removing from the equation anyone who would appreciate it. Pessimism can therefore inspire a deep compassion, borne out of the knowledge that nobody has any more value than anybody else (because everybody has none!). But even if pessimism of this kind did not have such an effect on the conscience, it would still be difficult, if not impossible, to defeat on rational grounds.
Last edited: