Choosing what we will order for dinner is literally, actually, objectively, and empirically a real choice.
And, given determinism, there was a 100% probability that we would be making a real choice.
Irrelevant. I am not talking about whether a choice would be made or not ...
You have repeatedly claimed that there is "no choice" in a deterministic system.
I am talking about the OUTCOME of that choice. Your attempt to move the goalposts demonstrates your dishonesty.
And you say that in the same breath in which you move the goalpost from "no choice" to the "OUTCOME of that choice".
And yet you can't comprehend that it works the other way around. "If that outcome was inevitable since the Big Bang, then it is AS IF we made a choice, but we never actually did, since a choice requires multiple possible options, yet one option being inevitable renders all other options as IMpossible, no matter how possible they may seem to us."
There is the restaurant menu. It contains multiple POSSIBLE options. Choosing one option never makes the other options IMPOSSIBLE. For example, although you actually chose the Chicken, you could have chosen the Steak instead. Under the given circumstances, you NEVER WOULD HAVE chosen the Steak, but you still COULD HAVE.
To test this, why don't you order the Steak for me. Thank you. And now you see that you had the ABILITY to order the Steak all along.
To say that you CAN order the Steak never implies that you WILL order the Steak. It simply means that the Steak was available on the menu as a real option that you COULD HAVE chosen IF you wanted to.
And yet the illusion of choice fits this perfectly as well. We experience an event which APPEARS to be the making of a choice.
Yes, it certainly APPEARS to be the making of a choice, just like it APPEARS to be us walking into the restaurant, and like it APPEARS to be us sitting down at a table, and like it APPEARS to be us opening the menu, and, sure enough, it APPEARS to be us telling the waiter what we have chosen for dinner.
"Appearances can be deceiving", but there is no reason to doubt the choosing any more than to doubt the walking or the sitting or the reading or the ordering.
All of the events appeared to happen in physical reality. And we may even assert that, given determinism, every event was reliably caused by prior events. For example, the walking to the table led to the sitting which led to reading the menu which led to making a choice which led to giving the waiter our order. Reliable causation. Oh, and of course, free will. Because no one other than us made the choice for us.
And, as it is with most choices, there was a single outcome, that was chosen by us from a list of multiple possibilities.
How in the world does this address the point I was making?
Sometimes, in a conversation, it is not just about the point you are making, but about the point someone else is making.
If it's inevitable, then it's going to happen no matter what. If it's going to happen no matter what, then it's not a free choice.
In order to assess what's "going to happen no matter what", we need to be clear on what is actually happening. That's the point of this lengthy explanation:
How do events become causally necessary/inevitable? By reliable causal mechanisms. These mechanisms can be very simple, like the mass of the Sun exerting gravitational force upon the Earth, causing it to travel around the Sun every year. Or, the causal mechanism may be very complex, like the DNA molecule that carries the plans and equipment to build a living organism. And then there is the living brain of an intelligent species, that can imagine, evaluate, and choose what it will cause to happen.
So, we have physical, biological, and rational causal mechanisms that we use to explain events, to understand "Why did this happen?". Determinism survives by assuming that each of these mechanisms is reliably deterministic within its own domain, and that every event will be reliably caused by some specific combination of physical, biological, and/or rational causation.
Rational causation performs logical operations, such as adding and choosing. Adding inputs two or more numbers, performs its function, and outputs a sum. Choosing inputs two or more options, compares the expected benefits of each option, and outputs a choice.
These rational operations enable humans to control what they will cause to happen in the real world. For example, we perform arithmetic to help us decide whether we can afford this new car. If we cannot afford it, we won't buy it. But if we can afford it, then we may decide to buy it. Buying the car causes changes in the real world, like the dealer ordering more cars and the factory building more cars. Perhaps others will see our new car and be motivated to buy themselves a new car.
So, these choices going on in our heads are part of the overall causation that makes determinism work. Within our personal domain of influence, our choices are part of the causal chain that makes future events causally necessary.
Part of the rational causal mechanism is the notion of possibilities. When we do not know the single thing that we WILL choose to do, we consider the many things that we CAN choose to do, imagine the likely outcomes of each option, and based on that evaluation select the option that we believe will be best. That becomes our choice.
In order to play its role, the mind must have two or more options to choose from, two or more things that it CAN choose to do. The fact that it will only choose ONE of these things does NOT mean that it COULD NOT have chosen the other.
The logic of the language is part of the choosing mechanism. It is how the human mind calculates and explains its choices.
If it's inevitable that we won't do them, then we CAN'T do them. We merely THINK we can.
THINKING that we CAN is sufficient. A possibility exists solely within the imagination. As soon as a "possibility" is made real in the physical world it is immediately renamed an "actuality". We cannot walk across a POSSIBLE bridge. We can only walk across an ACTUAL bridge. But this does not imply that a possibility is insignificant, because we cannot build an actual bridge without first imagining a possible bridge. The notion of possibilities enables the mind to invent, plan, and build new actual things, like our actual bridge that we can now walk across.
And this is why we cannot say things like, "If it's inevitable that we won't do them, then we CAN'T do them", because there will be many things that we inevitably won't do, which we still must consider to be things that we CAN do, in order for the human mind to choose what it will invent, plan, and build in the real world.
Or, for that matter, simply to choose what it will order for dinner. There must be multiple things that CAN be chosen on the way to determining the single thing that WILL be chosen. There must be multiple possibilities on our way to getting to the single actuality.
When viewed through determinism, we these thoughts about what we CAN do are part of the causal chain that are necessary to decide what we WILL do.
Otherwise, if we work under the idea that the universe is purely deterministic, then we'd have to say, "One of these outcomes WILL happen and all the others WILL NOT happen.
Correct. That is precisely what determinism implies. One option WILL be selected and the other options WILL NOT be selected.
But we CANNOT logically say that the other options COULD NOT be selected, because it is logically necessary that at least TWO options CAN be chosen in order for choosing to accomplish its work.
That's why this doesn't work:
The one outcome that WILL happen is the only one that CAN happen, because any outcome that WILL NOT happen CAN NOT happen. I don't know why some outcomes CAN NOT and WILL NOT happen, but that doesn't change the fact that there is only one possible outcome."
We cannot conflate what WILL happen with what CAN happen. Nor can we conflate the single ACTUAL outcome with the many POSSIBLE outcomes.
Those assumptions BREAK choosing, as we've demonstrated in the example:
Waiter: "What will you have for dinner tonight?"
Customer: "I don't know, what are my possibilities?"
Waiter: "In a deterministic world, there is only one thing that you can order."
Customer: "Oh. Well, what is the one thing that I can order?"
Waiter: "I do not know."
How many times do I have to tell you that this example is relying on the limited information available to humans? I even tried to demonstrate it but you had a hissy fit that I was making the waiter omniscient.
As a practical matter, it is ALWAYS the case that we are relying on the information that is available to us. None of us are omniscient (and that is why the omniscient waiter does not resolve the problem). We evolved the notion of possibility to logically deal with this uncertainty.
So you are saying we CAN do a thing when it is inevitable that we will never do that thing.
Exactly.
What sort of logic tells you that it's possible for you to do something that has a 0% chance of being done?
The same logic we use every day whenever we make a choice. When we do not yet know what we WILL do, we imagine what we CAN do, evaluate our options, and determine for ourselves what we WILL do.
At the beginning of the choosing operation, it is true, by logical necessity, that every option has a real chance of being chosen. Or, as you would say, "a probability > 0".
The decay of a specific radioactive atom. Now, I'm not talking about the process that the atom undergoes when it decays. I'm speaking of the event that triggers that process. Can you show it to me? Can you point to an atom and say, that atom will decay in 3... 2... 1... NOW!" and be correct? No you can't.
That is a problem of prediction, not a problem of causation. According to Wikipedia, there are several theories as to
what causes radioactive decay. But we cannot observe this happening in a single atom, because we have no way of looking at the specific cause within a specific atom. Thus, there is a problem in predicting this type of event.