What can be imagined is not necessarily what can happen, or what is even possible. Imagination is a flight of fancy, people can be superheroes, fly through the air, be invulnerable to bombs or bullets....
Correct. We can imagine many things that are impossible. So, a
real possibility is something that we can actually do,
if we choose to do it. An impossibility is something that we cannot do, even if we choose to.
In the restaurant, it is possible for me to have the steak, if I choose to. It is also possible for me to have the salad, if I choose to. So, there are two real possibilities.
It is also possible for me to choose the steak, if I prefer it over the salad. And, it is also possible for me to choose the salad, if I prefer it over the steak.
Both the steak and the salad are real possibilities, and it is really possible for me to choose either one.
I will choose the salad, because I had bacon and eggs for breakfast and a double cheeseburger for lunch. But the fact that I will choose the salad does not contradict the fact that I could have chosen the steak.
That's how the logic of the language works to enable us to adapt to environmental issues that evolution was unable to predict, like the fact that different restaurants have different menus. So, we have instead the ability to consider multiple things that we "can" do before deciding the single thing we "will" do.
So, let's not try to undo this evolutionary advantage.
Without possible alternate actions, where is the ability to choose otherwise? With no alternatives, where is freedom of will? Nowhere to be found, that's where.
Again, may I bring your attention to the restaurant's menu, filled with alternate possibilities. The claim that there are no alternate possibilities within a deterministic universe is easily proven to be false. And it is repeatedly proven every time we make a choice.
The question being; is neural architecture and its activity a matter of free will?
That depends. When the neural architecture actively chose to order the salad instead of the steak, was anyone pointing a gun at the neural architecture?
Like I've said before, "free will" is when the neural architecture chooses for itself what it will do, while free of coercion and undue influence.
The definition of free will does not change when you substitute "neural architecture" for "brain" or when you substitute "brain" for "person". They are all synonyms referring to the same object performing the same function.
The answer, based on numerous experiments, case studies, pathologies, conditions, etc, no it is not;
And that is only because philosophy has imposed upon them a notion of free will that is either supernatural or logically impossible. It has trapped them, and you, in a paradox, that even caught intelligent people like Albert Einstein.
When free will is understood with its original meaning, an event in which a person decides for themselves what they will do, free of coercion and undue influence (you know, the one used in courts and the one used by parents when they ask their child "Did you do that on purpose?"), then neuroscience consistently backs up the notion that the brain routinely chooses what the person will do next (whether consciously or unconsciously).
''This review deals with the physiology of the initiation of a voluntary movement and the appreciation of whether it is voluntary or not. I argue that free will is not a driving force for movement, but a conscious awareness concerning the nature of the movement. Movement initiation and the perception of willing the movement can be separately manipulated.
Movement is generated subconsciously, and the conscious sense of volition comes later, but the exact time of this event is difficult to assess because of the potentially illusory nature of introspection. Neurological disorders of volition are also reviewed.
The evidence suggests that movement is initiated in the frontal lobe, particularly the mesial areas, and the sense of volition arises as the result of a corollary discharge likely involving multiple areas with reciprocal connections including those in the parietal lobe and insular cortex.''' Volitional control of movement: The physiology of free will
Clinical Neurophysiology, Volume 118, Issue 6, Pages 1179-1192
M. Hallett
We can appreciate Mr. Hallett examining the sequence of volition and movement in simple experiments involving few if any choices. But he does not address the more common everyday sequence of events in real life. For example:
We did not walk to the restaurant and then make up a story to try to explain how we got there. We considered several places where we liked to eat, and decided upon a specific restaurant. That decision was when we first became aware of our volition to go to that restaurant. The motion of our legs followed that volition as we walked into the selected restaurant, sat down, browsed the menu of possibilities, and placed our orders. In this case, the volition preceded the motion of our legs, and it was that volition that causally determined that we would walk to the restaurant.
Decision-Making
''Decision-making is such a seamless brain process that we’re usually unaware of it — until our choice results in unexpected consequences. Then we may look back and wonder, “Why did I choose that option?” In recent years, neuroscientists have begun to decode the decision-making process. What they’re learning is shedding light not only on how the healthy brain performs complex mental functions, but also on how disorders, such as stroke or drug abuse, affect the process.’
''Researchers can study decision-making in animals. As monkeys decide which direction a moving target is headed, researchers record the activity in brain cells called neurons. These studies have helped to reveal the basis for how animals and humans make everyday decisions.''
Thanks to advances in technology, researchers are beginning to unravel the mysterious processes by which humans make decisions. New research is helping scientists develop:
A deeper understanding of how the human brain reasons, plans, and solves problems.
Greater insight into how sleep deprivation, drug abuse, neurological disorders, and other factors affect the decision-making process, suggesting new behavioral and therapeutic approaches to improve health.
Our brains appear wired in ways that enable us, often unconsciously, to make the best decisions possible with the information we’re given. In simplest terms, the process is organized like a court trial. Sights, sounds, and other sensory evidence are entered and registered in sensory circuits in the brain. Other brain cells act as the brain’s “jury,” compiling and weighing each piece of evidence. When the accumulated evidence reaches a critical threshold, a judgment — a decision — is made.''
Note that the person's own brain cells consider the evidence and make a decision. When that decision is made while free of coercion and undue influence, then the function called "free will". If it was coerced, then it is called "coercion".
No, compatibilists label decision making as 'free will' when no such conclusion is warranted.
Not at all. Compatibilists label decision making, "decision making". Whether the decision making was a matter of free will or not depends entirely upon whether the decision was free of coercion, insanity, and other undue influences.
If the decision making was free of coercion and undue influence, then it was an example of free will.
If the decision making was coerced, then it is not an example of free will, but rather an example of coercion.
Nobody is denying that the brain acquires and processes information, producing thoughts and actions as a result....it's only a question of whether this can be defined as free will.
Well, let's see. Was the brain's decision making free of coercion and undue influence? If it was, then it was a freely chosen "I will". If it was coerced or unduly influenced, then it was not.
QUOTE="DBT, post: 990533, member: 170"]
For the reasons given in numerous posts, the answer is: no the cognitive process does not qualify as being 'free will' because it lacks the right kind of regulatory control, ie, it is not being willed, it does not have alternatives. [/QUOTE]
"For the reasons given in numerous posts, the answer" is that the cognitive process qualifies as free will whenever it is deciding what the person will do, while free of coercion and undue influence.
And we have precisely the kind of regulatory control to decide that we will have the salad even though we could have had the steak. It's right there, staring us in the face.
The alternatives are on the menu, also right there, staring us in the face.
QUOTE="DBT, post: 990533, member: 170"]
It doesn't have alternatives because each and every state of incremental change is fixed by antecedents.[/QUOTE]
The appearance of alternatives happens to be one of those states, and one of the necessary antecedent events that causally fix the choice. The claim that they are not there among the antecedent events is debunked by simply looking at the menu.
QUOTE="DBT, post: 990533, member: 170"]
''Each state of the universe and its events are the necessary result of its prior state and prior events. ("Events" change the state of things.) Determinism means that events will proceed naturally (as if "fixed as a matter of natural law") and reliably ("without deviation"). - M. Edwards.
[/QUOTE]
It's nice that you have listened and understood and even quoted those words of mine. Now, if you could do the same with some of the other words that I've said.